The purpose of this paper is to support
the idea that pragmatism is still a productive resource for the study of
health and disease.
During his Italian lectures at the University of Roma in March 1992,
Hilary Putnam stated that at least two ideas typical Dewey pragmatism were
still fertile: the pre-eminence of practical reason and the holistic
interdependence between fact and theory and fact and value.
For Putnam as well as for Dewey pure data do not exist: nothing is given
if not in relation to an idea or an operational level that can be formally
expressed; from a formal point of view, both in natural languages and in
formalized ones, a fact is expressed in singular statements, while a
scientific law is a statement with a universal quantifier, but this
difference is not based on absolute irreducibility.
In other words: facts are operational in the sense that they are the
consequences of organization and choice; concepts are operational because
they are nothing but the proposals and plans intervention activities on
existing conditions. Each procedural choice in a survey is the consequence
of practical judgement and, for Dewey, each practical judgement is an
evaluation (i.e., in other words, the evaluation is engendered by a
criticism to problem-solving procedures). Putnam explicitly states that
Anglo-American philosophy has overlooked Dewey's insistence on the
intertwinement between facts and values, notwithstanding Morton White's
standing in Reunion in Philosophy .
Besides, pragmatism refuses the distinction between observational and
theoretical terms suggested by Carnap.
These theories are largely shared in current philosophical debates, as
hardly anybody supports pure neo-positivistic standings (as, for example,
Carnap's logical empiricism).
On the other hand, neo-positivistic premises, both explicit and implicit,
still play an important role, in medicine, in particular in Evidence-Based
Medicine (EBM), that is an approach to practising medicine in which the
clinician is aware of the evidence in support of clinical practice, and of
the strength of that evidence.
Evidence-Based Medicine is a process of problem-based learning. This
process involves:
1. Converting information needs into focused questions.
2. Efficiently tracking down the best evidence with which to answer the
question.
3. Critically appraising the evidence for validity and clinical usefulness.
4. Applying the results in clinical practice.
5. Evaluating performance of the evidence in clinical application.
The idea from which EBM stemmed was certainly excellent, as it meant that
medical choices (diagnosis, prognosis and treatment) were based on wide
experimentation whose results were made public in reliable magazines. As a
matter of fact, EBM is a process that can be standardized on well-verified
hypothesis, that evaluate the cost-benefit relation both for the patient
and the health system.
This implies the definition of diagnostic and therapeutic procedures that
can lead or even substitute the doctor both when he diagnoses and when he
prescribes a therapy. The founding idea of EBM is that the best scientific
proofs and in particular the results of experimentation in clinical
research, as in randomized controlled trials, can in principle determine
the correct therapy.
This is how a positivistic model works: the evidence of the facts, when
many and analysed with method, determine the theory, and the theory, if
applicable to the individual case, determines rational acts, i.e., in this
case, the therapy.
Against Evidence-Based Medicine, a "patient-centred medicine" is
gaining ground, maybe more in Europe than in the USA; this approach to
medicine refuses neo-positivistic presupposition. The philosophical
conception typical of pragmatism can play a key role in exposing the
implicit neo-positivistic presupposition so widespread among doctors,
while at the same time avoiding the risk that the philosophy of medicine
pick up hazy anti-scientific conceptions typical of the so-called
"alternative medicines".
There is a solid conceptual basis, both epistemological and pragmatic, to
discriminate between patient-centred medicine based on solid biological
basis and a simple ornamentation of the classical biomedical lines; this
basis is given by the thesis of the variety and uniqueness of the
biological systems and thus by the historical and irreversible character
of vital processes. The acceptance of this thesis is the most interesting
difference from the traditional positivistic formulation so grounded in
medicine.
Medicine considered with suspicion individual variety, to the point that
many authors prefer to use the word "variability"; the use of
this word implies a censorious attitude towards behaviours that are deemed
incoherent, whimsical, unstable or somehow not strict enough.
The reason is a simple one: the varied nature of biological phenomena
contradicts the primary requirement of any stringent scientific analysis,
that is the need to deal with an object of study, observation and
experimentation that is stable, unambiguous, clearly defined in its "essential"
features, that does not change depending on the case, and that can answer
to general scientific laws that are both necessary and fundamentally
deterministic. Variety and diversity are an insurmountable obstacle to the
possibility of generalizing data, both from observation and from clinical
practice.
The prevalent trends of contemporary medicine have
acted in different ways to diminish or conceal the role played by variety:
- taking in account the population rather than the individual being;
clinical trials, meta-analysis and systematic revisions are the more
powerful and consistent with EBM precepts the farther the specimens are
from individual dimension;
- accurately selecting the representative population sample of the
clinical study according to inclusion and exclusion criteria to enrol the
patients;
- working out diagnostic criteria and nosographic classifications that
refer to ideal and often abstract outline of "average" patients;
- identifying the significance, the practical importance and the
objectivity with the average statistics and with the main trends of the
analysed samples;
- leaving out a priori all confusing factors, such as subjectivity, that
can interfere with variables that are deemed meaningful and relevant, such
as with randomized trials control techniques, etc.;
- isolating knowledge from its context, that is, separating the object of
study from its natural environment (the laboratory) and from its relation
with the research worker (the emotional detachment of the professional
worker).
According to a widespread antinomy, the traditional biomedical model
-characterized by a sharp boundary between health and disease, by an
objective quantification of the cases, by methodological reductionism, by
a division between observation and therapeutic intervention- would be in
contrast with the bio-psycho-social model of an holistic-systemic kind,
that pays attention to the whole in an often blurred indistinct, esoteric,
"metaphysical" and anti-scientific way. This conception is well
summarized by the old Hippocratic aphorism, quoted by the varied galaxy of
contemporary alternative medicines, in theoretical opposition to the
traditional biomedical model: "Diseases are not real, we only have
ill patients". In reality, there is a dialectical relationship of
complementarity and positive competition between biological level and
psycho-social level, between tendency to illness and patient; this
complementarity overcomes the antinomy between holism and reductionism at
least as far as therapeutic practice is involved.
Patient-centred medicine on the other hand proposes a different attitude
towards clinical process: it is not a case chronicle anymore, but rather
an active listening to the story of the patient and to his experiences,
asking open questions and gathering different signals and not only the
symptoms, paying attention to non-verbal language. Patient-centred
medicine pays attention both to the pathology, in its biological sense,
and to the way the patient perceives his illness: the illness itself, even
if it is the same for all patients, and can thus be recognized, is
perceived also in the unique way it strikes each individual, that is, in
the way each individual patient reacts.Thus it becomes essential to
understand the patient, that is, to know what he knows and what he would
like to know, what he is expecting and what he fears, what he is willing
to do and what he could not stand doing, what he thinks his doctor can do
for him. Only if doctors give their patient's needs the fullest
consideration, can they really grasp the problems they have to face and
work out a shared strategy. The theoretical models of medicine can be
correctly applied only when the individual case is close enough to the
required conditions. It can be applied to medicine what Putman said of
physics: "The decision that conditions have been approximated well in
a given case -that it is even worthwhile to apply the idealized model to
this case- typically depends on unformalized practical knowledge."
Finally, patient-centered medicine is characterized by its understanding
of the point of view of the patient and by the attempt to understand the
way the patient reacts. The doctor does not limit his analysis to clinical
symptoms, but analyzes and accepts the patient's point of view, taking the
patient's experience into full consideration.
It can be worthwhile to notice that some neo-positivistic assumptions EBM
has uncritically accepted were already scrutinized by nineteenth century
French positivism. For example, even if Emile Durkheim developed his
analyses in a positivistic view according to which scientific theories are
based and can be deduced only from facts, he tried to investigate the
foundation of the distinction between normality and pathology, and
dedicated the entire III chapter of his The Rules of the Sociological
Method (1895) to this question. He wrote that both biological and
sociological normality cannot be identified according to average
statistical data. If the great majority of the individuals feature a
certain characteristic, this at the very most only represents a de facto
normality, while what is pathological can be defined only in relation to a
de jure normality, that is, to a model of optimum functionality. After a
careful analysis, Durkheim ruled out the possibility of defining illness
in relation to the degree of pain, or to a perfect adaptation of the
organism to the environment, or to a mere probability of survival. He
defined the normality of phenomena and processes - both biological and
sociological - according to positive science (what can be considered
harmless for the health of the individual or the good functioning of
society, that is, a de jure normality), that is, in relation to "the
conditions of existence of the species analyzed, both as a mechanically
necessary effect of those conditions, and as a means for an organism to
adjust to them" "(La normalité du phénomène sera expliquée
par cela seul qu'il sera rattaché aux conditions d'existence de l'espèce
considérée, soit comme un effet mécaniquement nécessaire de ces
conditions, soit comme un moyen qui permet aux organismes de s'y adapter
)". Thus he was sure that it was possible to determine normality in
the area of the positive science (as a non-evaluative one), even if it was
not possible to determine it statistically or inductively.
The positivistic dogma of a science based only on facts gained force in
the interwar years, when the philosophy of science was dominated by
neo-positivism: the philosophers of the Vienna Circle urged by a strong
anti-metaphysical drive, set themselves the task to achieve the great
ideal of a science totally based on empirical experience, a science whose
theories would be ensued only from what can be perceived by the senses
through the application of mathematics and formal logic. It is the ideal
of a non-evaluative, objective, incontrovertible science that is free from
metaphysical, cultural and moral assumptions. It is the reassuring but
dangerous temptation to consider facts as sacred, forgetting that they are
theory-laden or theory-soaked, as Popper says. To deny the antinomic
nature of the difference between facts and theories, that is common both
to Popper and to pragmatism, is a feature already present in Medieval
philosophy, according to which "talia sunt obiecta qualia
determinantur a predicatis suis", if we accept that predicate means
the conceptual categories we use when we interpret facts.
As everybody knows, the subsequent developments of the philosophy of
science, from Popper to Quine, definitely showed the illusoriness of the
neo-positivistic dream of a science objectively based on pure facts. They
also showed the failure of inductive logic, in the sense that also the
most refined systems of inductive logic, as those developed by Jaakko
Hintikka , were not able to determine a satisfactory confirmation function
of scientific hypothesis based on the evidence of observational data.
Nevertheless, in contemporary medicine, as I already noticed, important
positivistic influences continue to persist.
The most important prejudice, that often works at unconscious level, is
the tendency to interpret illness as a kind of malfunctioning of the
biological machine, i.e. of the human body, and this malfunctioning is
interpreted as something objectively measurable, in the sense that any
competent subject can recognize this situation, notwithstanding his
personal beliefs or preferences. The root of this prejudice directly stems
from an idea of rationality that is typical of logical positivism: only
theories that are verified according to a set of rules or to a method are
considered as rational; this set of rules or method, "although one
that philosophers of science have admittedly not yet succeeded in fully
formalizing" is the only guarantee to rationally accept the theories
themselves.
Statements testable by the methods of mathematics, logic and empirical
sciences would count as meaningful; all other statements (i.e. the
subjective experiences of the patient as they are told to the doctor) are
"pseudo-statements" or disguised nonsense, and as such are
simply ignored by EBM.
This idea of disease as an objective malfunctioning cannot be accepted for
many different reasons:
1. "Malfunctioning" or "failure" have a meaning only
if the perfect working condition or normality is univocally determined.
When the definition of disease itself is under discussion, normality
should be defined starting from the concept of health. C. Boorse , one of
the main supporters of the reductionist model, defines health as a typical
"means-end hierarchy" of interconnected functional systems that
support life; but how is it possible to ascertain the typical hierarchy,
the normal functioning? It would not be possible to answer this question
empirically or statistically, as it certainly cannot be stated that the
features to be found in the majority of the population define normality
and thus health. If the vast majority of the world population would be
afflicted by a certain endemic disease, it still would not be possible not
to consider it a disease.
2. In principle, every being is different from any other: if two cars of
the same make and model were analyzed and measured with extreme accuracy,
they would show some trifling differences in various components. Anyway,
the absence of serious flaws in their making makes these differences
unimportant, both when performance standards have to be defined and when a
failure has to be repaired. On the other hand, the differences between a
person and any other person are not unimportant and cannot be ignored
neither in diagnosis nor in treatment. These differences can be ascribable
to three different sets of reasons:
a. As every living being, man preserves in his memory the previous phases
of his life, unlike inorganic entities. That means that an atom of oxygen
combines with other atoms to form a molecule independently of its past
history: Potentially, two atoms of the same substance are identical. On
the other hand, vital processes have a historical, irreversible nature.
Thus there are no two identical living beings. Illnesses leave
irreversible marks on the organic structure, i.e. they modify the
information an organism has at least as far as the neuroendocrine and
immune systems are involved.
b. There are individual differences in the immune system.
c. There are individual differences in the functional organization of the
brain that are not due only to biological causes. Edelman thinks that the
dynamic core of the brain (that is, that subset of neurons in the
thalamus-cortical system that are closely interconnected and that form the
biological structure of awareness) is different from person to person even
as far as how many and which cerebral cells are involved: the individual
-psychic- "history" of the brain somehow determines its material
organization.
These three sets of individual differences follow an order of decreasing
universality: the first (biological differences) is typical of all living
beings; the second (differences in the immune system) is typical of
animals in relation to how evolved they are; the third is particularly
relevant only for man.
3. The subjective perception of the illness itself must be included among
the elements that determine the features of an illness. Notwithstanding
the presence of the same symptoms and the same tests readings, two people
may perceive their illness in a different way, with effects on the course
of the illness itself and the effectiveness of the treatment.
4. The idea of disease also depends on the cultural context. This is
evident when we compare the social perception of disease in contemporary
western society to the idea ancient pre-Columbian or Indian or Chinese
civilizations had.
To sum up, what contribution can a philosophy of
science based on pragmatism provide nowadays to the definition of the idea
of disease? What misunderstandings can it help dissolve?
1.First of all, it might be noticed that it is not totally useless to look
for an accurate definition of disease. Usually definitions may play a very
conventional role in a theory, and then they need not be discussed. Still,
the definition of a concept may as well be considered as a synthesis of
acquired cognitions in a certain scientific area, if it is functional to
delimit the body of the phenomena it wants to define;
2.Hippocrates is thought to have declared: "Diseases are not real, we
only have ill patients". This statement can play an important role in
clinical practice, as an invitation not to overlook the individual
features of each patient. But the Hippocratic thesis, above all if we
consider it in the way it has been treated nowadays by historians of
science, even prestigious ones as Mirco Grmeck, may be misleading for
medical science and it is unacceptable also from the point of view of
pragmatism. The Sorbonne historian stated that illnesses are only models
to explain reality and not elements that constitute it, but this thesis
may lead to a short-sighted instrumental use: a scientific theory is such
just because it discovers laws, i.e. relations, between cause and effect,
in this case between agent of infection and disease.
3.Some of the definitions that philosophers of science have suggested are
only unsatisfactory shortcuts. Pedersen and other philosophers of science
of hermeneutic inclination declare that it is totally useless to look for
a definition of disease. They justify their statement by saying that this
word has many different meanings that look alike, in the way Wittgenstein
pointed in his Philosophical Investigations, and that use only can
determine these meanings. From the point of view of logics, the word
"disease" could be a vague, but not an ambiguous one. . In the
same direction move those who, like Kraupl-Taylor and Engelhardt , try to
define illness not on the basis of a biological condition, but in relation
to how worried the patient or the doctor are. On the contrary, the
definition of disease may be useful only if it gives the foundations of
the reality itself.
4.The point of view of pragmatism is useful to disprove the thesis of
those who define disease only in relation to the organism isolated from
the surrounding environment. As the capability of living beings to change
the intensity of their functions opposing the consequences of
environmental mutations allowed them to survive and reproduce in the
course of evolution, disease would be identified with the fact that an
organism is not able to keep its homeostasis in relation to varying
environmental conditions (once the organism is not able to further change
the intensity of its functions, it is obliged to modify its interior
environment).
5.The point of view of pragmatism is useful to disprove the thesis of
those who define disease only in relation to a reduced efficiency of the
organism. Combining the results of thermodynamic theories with
evolutionism, some said that the biological structures selected by
evolution are perfect to maximize the conservation of energy; as a
consequence, they tend to reduce the entropy in the organism. Thus, a
process can be defined as pathological if it increases the entropy, which
means a diminished efficiency of the organism (the positive side of this
point of view is that it correctly includes also chronic illnesses in the
general definition of disease). The attitudes presented at paragraphs 4and
5 both stem from the idea of disease exclusively as "objective
malfunctioning".
6.Besides these two conceptions, that define disease as a purely
biological fact, the psycho- social paradigm has gained ground. This
interpretation looks for remote causes of disease and accepts that the
definition of pathology implies criteria based on values. The
psycho-social paradigm is strongly criticized both by the philosophers of
science and by famous clinicians because for them it mixes up different
levels of medicine. For example, Federspill states that the historical and
social features and moral values are relevant only for medical art, i.e.
clinical practice and therapy , but they are absolutely irrelevant for
biological medicine, as science is non-evaluative, it only has an
explanatory function. This kind of criticism cannot be accepted from the
point of view of pragmatism: in the case of medicine in particular, the
theoretical level is not self standing, rather, it is connected with the
idiographic level (diagnosis) and the practical level (therapy), also
because, as a matter of fact, diagnostics and therapeutic needs often
guide pure research, spurring further analysis, revision and clarification
of the theoretical view.
The footnotes can be read in pdf or word version of this
paper
|