"It has been widely held that, in
the history of the human race, judgements of right and wrong originated in
the fact that primitive men or their non-human ancestor had certain
feelings towards certain classes of actions (…) so that, in a sense, our
moral judgements were developed out of mere feelings. And I can see no
objection to the supposition that this was so. But, then, it seems also to
be often supposed that, if our moral judgements were developed out of
feelings - if this was their origin - they must still at this moment be
somehow concerned with feelings: that the developed product must resemble
the germ out of which it was developed in this particular respect. And
this is an assumption for which there is, surely, no shadow of ground"
As Moore thinks that the view about the origin of moral judgements is
different from the one about ontological status of moral judgements, even
if the two views are very liable to be confused with one another, so I
think that the account about the origin of normative judgements relating
to how we ought to act is different from the account about what normative
judgements are.
When you have to solve a problem, you have to deal with information.
Information comes from the outside world into the sensory registers in the
human brain. This input consists of things perceived by our senses. We are
not consciously aware of most of the things we perceive; we become aware
of them only if we consciously direct our attention to them. When we do
focus our attention on them, they are placed in our working memory (short-term
memory). Each piece of information that comes into this short-term storage
area, if one does not forget it, is moved out of this area by being
shifted to long-term memory.
We all take in information through our senses and this information is
processed by our brain resulting in behaviour, our response to the
situation. We all have the same sensory systems, yet we may respond very
differently to the same input information. We have all experienced
situations in which people have very different reactions to the same
inputs. Different processing can result from people accessing different
reference experiences from their personal history memory or utilizing
different processing patterns. But it is important to analyse,
independently from any difference, the essential structure of normative
judgements relating to how one ought to act, i.e. the nature of the
concept of the normative judgement.
A human being can solve a problem or satisfy a desire because, in first
place, he is able to figure out how the things will be after his actions.
If the situation is different from what he wishes and has pictured, he has
to select an immediate aim, i.e. something that is desired immediately for
itself (if one is hungry and he does not have food, he establishes finding
food as an immediate aim: the aim is principium in intentione et terminus
in executione). If an aim is not immediately available, one must choose
adequate means to get it, i.e. he formulates a normative judgement
relating to how he ought to act, on the basis of the own belief and the
own memory. This is the origin of normative judgements and this is an
essential feature of practical reason, or, using Kant's phrase, of "reason
in its practical employment".
Any normative judgements is based on a belief and there is, as Hume says
in the Treatise, a close correlation between belief and passions: "As
belief is almost absolutely requisite to the exciting our passions, so the
passions in their turn are very favourable to belief; and not only such
facts as convey agreeable emotions, but very often such as give pain, do
upon that account become more readily the objects of faith and opinion (…)
When any affecting object is presented, it gives the alarm, and excites
immediately a degree of its proper passion; especially in persons who are
naturally inclined to that passion. This emotion passes by an easy
transition to the imagination; and diffusing itself over our idea of the
affecting object, makes us form that idea with greater force and vivacity,
and consequently assent to it" (I, III, 10, p. 120) .
The predominance of a belief is determined by the intensity of the passion
that is correlated. The belief, which is a constitutive element of a
normative judgement relating to how one ought to act, is able to excite
new desires and interests. By the memory and the custom, the normative
judgements can become a general rule. It is important, before dealing with
the formation of general rules, to examine the place of pleasure in the
account about the origin of normative judgements.
According to Hume, any passion, not only the direct passions, is founded
on pleasure or pain:
"The chief spring or actuating principle of the human mind is
pleasure or pain; and when these sensations are remov'd, both from our
thought and feeling, we are, in a great measure, incapable of passion or
action, of desire or volition. The most immediate effects of pleasure and
pain are the propense and averse motions of the mind; which are
diversified into volition, into desire and aversion, grief and joy, hope
and fear, according as the pleasure or pain changes its situation, and
becomes probable or improbable, certain or uncertain, or is consider'd as
out of our power for the present moment." (III, III, 1, p. 574).
According to Hume's hedonistic view, the pleasure is the ultimate account
of any human act of volition, it is not only the cause of the origin of
normative judgements:
"It appears evident that the ultimate ends of human actions can never,
in any case, be accounted for by reason, but recommend themselves entirely
to the sentiments and affections of mankind, without any dependance on the
intellectual faculties. Ask a man why he uses exercise; he will answer,
because he desires to keep his health. If you then enquire, why he desires
health, he will readily reply, because sickness is painful. If you push
your enquiries farther, and desire a reason why he hates pain, it is
impossible he can ever give any. This is an ultimate end, and is never
referred to any other object. (…) And beyond this it is an absurdity to
ask for a reason. It is impossible there can be a progress in infinitum;
and that one thing can always be a reason why another is desired.
Something must be desirable on its own account, and because of its
immediate accord or agreement with human sentiment and affection."
If it is evident that pleasure and pain are the cause of the origin of
normative judgements, this statement does not imply that if something must
be desirable on its own account, it is so because of its immediate
agreement with human sentiment and affection. The human mind is not only a
set of atomistic mental images and representations, as Hume thought, which
are united by a "gentle force". Before Hume, the psychological
hedonism, the view according to which desiring a thing, and finding it
pleasant, are, in the strictness of language, two modes of naming the same
psychological fact, was already criticized and disapproved by Joseph
Butler, who, in the eleventh Sermon preached at the Rolls Chapel in London,
in a Sunday of Advent in 1726 , held that it is normal for a man to have
an instinct of self-interest, which leads him to seek his own good, and
equally normal for him to have an instinct of benevolence, which leads him
to seek the good of others individually and generally, and that the two
aims do not in fact conflict.
Our conscious active impulses are so far from being always directed
towards the attainment of pleasure or avoidance of pain for ourselves,
that we can find everywhere in consciousness extra-regarding impulses,
directed towards something that is not pleasure, nor relief from pain;
and, indeed, a most important part of our pleasure depends upon the
existence of such impulses. As Sidgwick wrote, such impulses "are in
many cases so far incompatible with the desire of our own pleasure that
the two kinds of impulse do not easily coexist in the same moment of
consciousness; and more occasionally (but by no means rarely) the two come
into irreconcilable conflict, and prompt to opposite courses of
action." . It is important to point out that the familiar instances
of conflict between impulses directed towards the attainment of pleasure
and some extra-regarding impulse are not paradoxes and illusions to be
explained away, but phenomena which the analysis of our consciousness in
its normal state, when there is no such conflict, would lead us to expect.
If we are continually acting from impulses whose immediate objects are
something other than our own pleasure, it is quite natural that we should
occasionally yield to such impulses when they prompt us to an
uncompensated sacrifice of pleasure.
Therefore if we want to understand the essential structure of the
normative judgements, if we want to get a constitutive account about
normative judgement, we have to analyse the relation between the will and
the desire, disregarding the role of pleasure in the determination of the
will. A constitutive account cannot be captured in purely modal terms.
Giving a constitutive account is not the same as specifying modally
necessary and sufficient conditions. For example, being a type of polygon
that can be inscribed in a circle regardless of the lengths of its sides
is necessary and sufficient for being a three-sided polygon. But a correct
constitutive account of a triangle will plausibly mention the latter but
not the former property.
Not all modal determinants of a phenomenon are constitutive determinants.
One who agrees with that point might nevertheless conceive of a
philosophical account as an attempt to specify constitutive determinants
of the target phenomenon that make up a non-redundant supervenience base
for the phenomenon. A philosophical account into this form leaves out
elements that are modally redundant, but may be explanatorily or
ontologically significant. For example, when a constitutive account has
multiple levels, the different levels could be modally redundant.
Formulating the account as a specification of a base of constitutive
determinants will therefore flatten the account into a single level. The
pleasure is a modal determinant for the will: one can conceive it as a
necessary and sufficient condition for the origin of normative judgements,
but a constitutive account about the normative judgment is possible
disregarding the role of pleasure in the determination of the will.
A normative judgement is usually a consequence of a rational judgement
about the suitableness of some means for the aim that a rational being
desires to reach; i.e. reason in its practical employment is usually an
instrumental reason. The principle of the instrumental reason is
analytical because it is constitutive of the act of will: he who
undertakes to choose an end, he undertakes at the same time to choose the
means to get that end. Acting in conformity with the principle of
instrumental reason is the consequence of the normative nature of the
agent's mental states, when the agent feels his acts as his own ones. But
a rational being can use his reason even to judge about what is desirable
as an aim in itself, and not only as a means to another end. We can name
factual ultimate aim the aim that is desired only as an aim in itself, and
it is never regarded as a means. From a logical point of view, the
existence of the factual ultimate aim is postulated by the order of
priority according to which a human being ranges his immediate and
intermediate aims, even if many persons are not aware about what their
factual ultimate aim is. If the order of priority according to which the
aims are ranged is rational, then the factual ultimate aim is known by the
agent. Can the factual ultimate aim be conceived as a non-moral intrinsic
value? The meaning of the term "value" that I use is the same
that we find in David Lewis' account of value, according to which "necessarily,
for all x, x is a value if and only if under ideal conditions we would be
disposed to value x".
The distinction between fact and value, in league with such equally grand
and obscure distinctions, as those between objectivity and subjectivity
and between receptiveness and activity in the knowledge development, has
been vastly influential. Yet it appears on inspection to rest upon
surprisingly discretionary foundations. If it is true that any value
judgement is a normative judgement, the question about the ground of
normative judgements is posed. About this topic, the is-ought thesis (or
Hume's law), according to which no normative sentence is logically
inferable from a consistent set of purely descriptive (non-normative)
sentences, has been stated by numerous philosophers. The acceptance of
Hume's law as a logical-linguistic thesis (the thesis according to which
it is impossible to derive a normative sentence from two premises which
does not contain an obligation operator, or any other normative operator)
does not involve that the difference between descriptive and normative
level is based on absolute irreducibility.
The great division between prescriptive and descriptive in itself is
neither true nor false and the is-ought thesis (i.e. the impossibility to
logically derive prescriptive sentences from descriptive premises) is
definitely correct, but on the condition of having chosen to adopt the
great division. Therefore the statement "all sentences of a
formalized language are divided into descriptive and prescriptive" is
not analytical, (his opposite is not contradictory) but it must be assumed
(with prescriptive value) if you want to analyse the language of morals (as
many philosophers of morals do) or if you want to develop, for instance, a
deontic logic. The attempts to disprove Hume's law on the
logical-linguistic plan have decidedly failed and therefore the critics of
the ethical non-cognitivism can only follow the two remaining roads: (a)
Hume's law, valid from the formal point of view, is however "empty",
since the purely descriptive plan does not exist; (b) Hume's law is
irrelevant from a practical point of view, as there are some evaluative
sentences universally approved (of the type: "it is better to be
healthy than sick" or "you must do what it is right"). To
get a constitutive account of the normative judgement we have to choose
the first road and therefore we assume that the normative judgements are
grounded in intrinsic features of human believing or intending.
The factual ultimate aim could be regarded by a human being as better than
any other his aims, according to a relational view of good. It is
important to understand that relationalism is distinct from ethical
relativism. Volume, for instance, is a relational concept: nothing is
absolutely voluminous. But the two-place predicate "x is more
voluminous than y" has an objectively determinate extension. Perhaps
the simplest relational theory of goodness is that of Hobbes, who held
that to call something good is always to refer to someone's good, and that
the only sense in which something can be good for someone is that he
desires it for its own sake. This theory is deeply misleading and it is
incapable of capturing important features of value judgement. Often we
wish to raise questions about the intrinsic desirability of the
intermediate ends that now are the main focus of our desires, even after
any mistake in the use of the instrumental reason have been corrected. And
so it is about the factual ultimate aim: one can wonder whether his
factual aim is part of one's good. For instance, a niggard who uses
perfectly and without mistakes the instrumental reason to get money can
raise questions about the intrinsic desirability of wealth. For a niggard
wealth is the factual ultimate aim, but is it an intrinsic value?
We can name the ultimate aim normative ultimate aim if, and only if, it is
an intrinsic value, i.e. if it is the objective interest of the agent. We
can define the intrinsic value as what is desired by an ideal agent who is
endowed with unqualified cognitive and imaginative powers, and full
factual and nomological information about his physical and psychological
constitution. Such ideal agent, if he were, would have only rational
desires. The normative ultimate aim is the factual ultimate aim of an
ideal agent and it is his objective interest. If one were to become fully
convinced that one's desire for his aim is not supported by right
reflection upon the facts, one presumably would this to be a count against
acting in conformity of the desire. Using the reason to judge whether the
factual ultimate aim is an intrinsic value for the agent is a
non-instrumental use of reason, even if we are always regarding normative
judgements in both the cases.
Is the normative ultimate aim necessarily a moral normative ultimate aim?
The answer to this question depends on the view about the intrinsic value.
Is the intrinsic value always a moral value? In the second half of the
twentieth century, many ethical theorists sake to capture the special
character of moral evaluation by identifying a moral point of view that is
impartial, but equally concerned with all those potentially affected.
Other philosophers have come to a similar view by investigating the sort
of reason treated as relevant in moral discourse. They held that moral
norms reflect a certain kind of rationality, rationality not from the
point of view of any particular individual, but from the social point of
view. In the nineteenth century, Henry Sidgwick distinguished between
egoistic hedonism and universalistic hedonism, i.e. the utilitarianism.
The egoistic hedonism is the method of determining reasonable conduct that
implies the adoption of his own greatest happiness as the ultimate end of
each individual's actions . In this view the ultimate end could be
conceived as a non-moral intrinsic value, if we hold that the greatest
surplus of pleasure over pain is an intrinsic value for an agent, i.e. his
objective interest. While, on the contrary, by utilitarianism he means the
ethical theory, that the conduct which, under any given circumstances, is
objectively right, is that which will produce the greatest amount of
happiness on the whole; that is, taking into account all whose happiness
is affected by the conduct . He conceives the ultimate end of an
utilitarian as a very moral intrinsic value. All these points of views
assume that an intrinsic value for a human being is not necessary a moral
value.
On the opposite, according to the aristotelian-thomistic view of ethics,
only moral value is the intrinsic value for an agent, i. e. his objective
interest: aiming at self-fulfilment is the same that aiming to moral
values.
This account of the normative judgement postulates the negation of the
absolute heterogeneity between fact and value, as the pragmatism holds.
During his Italian lectures at the University of Roma in March 1992,
Hilary Putnam stated that at least two ideas typical Dewey pragmatism were
still fertile: the pre-eminence of practical reason and the holistic
interdependence between fact and theory and fact and value. For Putnam as
well as for Dewey pure data do not exist: nothing is given if not in
relation to an idea or an operational level that can be formally expressed;
from a formal point of view, both in natural languages and in formalized
ones, a fact is expressed in singular statements, while a scientific law
is a statement with a universal quantifier, but this difference is not
based on absolute irreducibility.
In other words: facts are operational in the sense that they are the
consequences of organization and choice; concepts are operational because
they are nothing but the proposals and plans intervention activities on
existing conditions. Each procedural choice in a survey is the consequence
of practical judgement and, for Dewey, each practical judgement is an
evaluation (i.e., in other words, the evaluation is engendered by a
criticism to problem-solving procedures). Putnam explicitly states that
Anglo-American philosophy has overlooked Dewey's insistence on the
intertwinement between facts and values. Besides, about epistemology,
pragmatism refuses the distinction between observational and theoretical
terms suggested by Carnap and by neopositivistic philosophers. Carnap and
neopositivistic philosophers were non-cognitivist about values, meaning
they thought that value statements were cognitively meaningless. Dewey, on
the other hand, believed that evaluative judgments were integral to
scientific inquiry. For Dewey, inquiry is rooted in practice: "All
controlled inquiry contains a practical factor; an activity of doing and
making which reshapes antecedent existential material which sets the
problem of inquiry" . The judgments of scientists are not merely
descriptive or factual assertions, but also judgments of practice, i.e.
"decisions as to what to do and what means to employ in doing it"
Because inquiry is an intervention into a problematic situation, decisions
must be made as to the appropriate means of resolving that situation. The
inquirer is thus constantly evaluating possible courses of action.
According to Dewey, any genuine deliberation proceeds by institution and
examination of alternative courses of activity and consideration of their
respective consequences, which are always operational rather than
terminal; for Dewey means and ends are always interdependent in inquiry.
This interdependence between means and ends is the ground for the view
according to which any normative judgement has the same structure and
nature, irrespective of the fact that it is a judgement about a means, or
an immediate, intermediate or ultimate aim: purely theoretical or
descriptive judgements do not exist, but they all postulate some kind of
normative structure in the use of the human reason. Knowing and
understanding something allows and encourages every human being to have a
reason to act, i.e. a consideration that counts in favour of an action or
attitude. The normative judgements are grounded in intrinsic features of
believing or intending and surely they are an irremovable element in
constitutive aims of believing or intending.
Many philosophers have claimed that the intentional is normative (this
claim is the analogue, within the philosophy of mind, of the claim that is
often made within the philosophy of language, that meaning is normative.)
The "intentional" is a subset of the mental. All conscious
mental states are about something; they are "directed towards"
or "concerned with" something. For example, some of my beliefs
are about Italy; some of my intentions are about going to Rome; and some
of my feelings are about God. These mental states all have intentional
content, and so may be called "intentional states" . The
normative judgements are grounded in intrinsic features of the intentional
states of the human mind. Our intentional states are always correlated
with our dispositions; when I refer to our "dispositions" here,
I do not mean to focus exclusively on our behavioural dispositions; I mean
to include our mental dispositions as well, such as our dispositions to
revise our beliefs and intentions in response to various conditions. For
instance when a human being possesses a concept, he has a disposition to
use this concept to formulate judgements. This disposition is part of what
it is about you that makes it the case that you possess a concept. If one
possesses a concept, the dispositions in virtue of which one possesses it
must be rational dispositions. Then we can hold that the normative nature
of our judgement is intrinsic with our rational dispositions: the rational
dispositions of our mind have essential normative properties, even if we
must not identify mental properties with their normative role in mental
activity.
The footnotes can be read in .pdf or word version of this
paper
|